Possibility and Necessity

Propositions can be true in different ways. Some propositions are necessarily true, in the sense that they could not possibly be false. (Tautologies are necessarily true, for example.) Other propositions are contingently true, in the sense that they happen to be true although they could have been false. Similarly, some propositions are necessarily false, in the sense that they couldn’t possibly be true, while others are contingently false: they happen to be false, although they could have been true. These different ways of being true or false are sometimes called modes of truth and falsity.

Modal logic is designed to deal with logical structure involving the modes of truth and falsity. More broadly, modal logic deals with the notions of possibility and necessity. However, the words ‘possible’ and ‘necessary’ can mean different things, and it is important to distinguish between these meanings. There are numerous types of modality, corresponding to different meanings of ‘possibility’ and ‘necessity’:

Any of the above varieties of possibility and necessity can be represented by modal logic. However, we must exercise caution when dealing with arguments that involve more than one type of possibility or necessity. When an argument employs more than one sense of possibility, watch out for fallacies of equivocation! (The fallacy of equivocation is the mistake of using an ambiguous word to mean different things in different parts of an argument.) Consider the following example:

The laws of physics imply that if it’s possible to travel faster than the speed of light, then it’s possible to travel backwards in time. It is possible to travel faster than light, in the sense that there is nothing logically contradictory about moving faster than 300,000 km/s. Therefore, it’s possible to travel backwards in time.

Although the argument resembles the valid form modus ponens, the first premise involves physical possibility, while the second premise refers to logical possibility. So, the second premise does not really mean the same thing as the antecedent of the conditional. The argument is not a genuine instance of modus ponens.